Differences John Rahn In this age of difference, a "postmodern" era which (on the surface) proclaims its difference from the Modern with all the naive historicizing fervor of any past avant-garde, this fin-de-siecle which hysterically celebrates the centrifugal as it sees increasing global dominion and concentration of capital and (not coincidentally) an increasingly Americanized world pop "culture," dancing out its fatal anxiety in a purgative tarantella, Panic evacuating its every essence -- in such surroundings, stepping carefully in counterpoint, do we dare make a difference? For every act of difference is power. Power flows like sap in the humble reeds that whisper in our ear, a thousand things. When we then act to make a difference, power draws the line: the line in the sand, the cut in the throat of the sacrifice, the boundary within which is one thing, and without which is an other. After we have acted to make a difference, Power turns its maned head in our direction. A work of art is an act of power. If we were to ask Difference what its essence was, it would be embarrassed. In fact, Difference could not bear it. If Difference thought it had a nature, it would get carried away in all directions. We can instead ask each difference simple questions, such as: Where does it draw the line? How, and why, does it draw the line? Does it draw more than one? Of what shape? Of what function? To what end? In what relations? And perhaps the answers to such questioning will form individual differences into regions, packs, swarms, congeries, ethnicities, or modes of differences, which in turn will inform thought about art. Gerardo's Latino Rap act -- as in the music video "Rico. Suave." -- draws a circle named Gerardo, and another circle around Gerardo's genitals. The genital circle depends, interlinked, from Gerardo's; but in two other senses, Gerardo's circle contains the genital, and the genital circle contains Gerardo's. There is very little difference between the two circles. Only in the first of these senses does Gerardo open at all, but only to himself: the interlinked circles of Gerardo and genitals are each other's other (with a small "o"), where neither is inside the other. But in the two other senses, Gerardo and his genitals are each other's content, each both the inside and the outside: stasis. The image of a sphere, or hypersphere, a milkily opaque globe into which comes no intrusion from the world, and from which comes no minutest excrescence. The image of a Christmas-tree ornament, or an unfertilized egg, ornamental and monoecious. The kind of object it is safe to play with. It can have no consequences. It is an object designed for mass consumption, neither nourishing nor obviously poisonous. Gerardo's Egg typifies an identity which is not an identity. Because it is its own outside, it is inaccessible and empty. There is little to differentiate it; it has no features. It is not an individual (though undivided) because it does not actively participate in an individuating web of relations. It is not a person, because it has neither a culture nor a will. How could it have a culture, without participation in a culture? How could it have a will, when there is no field of play in which a will could operate? It is a mere toy tossed in the surf of a cultural environment that can never penetrate it (or it would sink). It is a subject made object. But it is not a complex object. Though its existence reflects its constituting society, it is not Lacan's specular other-with-a-small-o, not alien, not ego, because it is not even a (convincing) simulacrum of subjectivity. Madonna, corporate package that she is, offers another kind of I-deal. Each of Madonna's music videos engages its own nexus of social and ideological issues. The series of music videos gives the impression of an artist, a person, working her way through themes offered her by her life experience: her father, her familial religion, racism, environmentalism, prisons, and always, of course, sexuality. There is a development from work to work. Each work internally is not inert, but active in a way that is sufficiently polysemous to bear interpretation, or active reception. The line Madonna draws is a "ligne de fuite," a line of flight or vanishing-line, always escaping to another plane. The one semiotic constant is her femininity, or at least, her sexuality, which she wears like a mask -- like a guest at a masquerade party who wears her own face. In her music videos, there is a counterpoint between the musical and the visual developments. The music, which itself is neither complex nor innovative, provides continuity for the fragmented, rapid-cut video montage which primarily conveys Madonna's papier-machİ shell of personae, the technique by which she achieves her "lignes de fuite." Each screen shows a plane of consistency; each of Madonna's lines of flight escapes to a new one. Her work exemplifies a difference always in flux and always at the surface. The line is drawn not in the sand, that would be too stable, but on the screen, and redrawn.... Which is her side, our side, the other side? <1> And yet there is a Madonna discernible behind this fretwork screen. The saturated surface of pop-culture intertextuality is gathered up, enfolded, enveloped. The n-dimensional construct of planes of consistency created by her lines of flight is packaged in an n+1-th dimension, the artist's persona behind the papier-machİ shell, and this in turn intersects a plane in a higher dimension, which is the native emblemicity, the ethnicity of her work. This multiple capture of the fluttering bird threatens to trivialize its subject. Can the bird fly free? An artwork can draw a line between two groups of people. It can do this intentionally, as in certain political or racist productions; it can fall "naturally" into this role, as in, say, Country and Western music or any folk music; or it can be objectified and used as a tool for drawing a line, like a national anthem. Almost any music can fall prey to such divisional instrumentality. The motives for drawing the line may be characterized as positive (pride in nationality, race, class, ethnicity, or education) or negative (to help enforce the exclusion of people on the other side). The music can then be regarded as representing these divisions and identifications, these nuances of social and cultural structure. Music criticism (of the academic, intellectual sort) is just beginning to be fascinated by such semeiosis, spurred on by the criticism of literature and art, the perspective of ethnomusicology, and the example of Continental thinkers such as Barthes, Eco, and Foucault, to name only a few. The play of signifiers within any of Madonna's music videos is the very stuff of that art, the material internal to it in terms of which it structures itself, so that such criticism is both appropriate and inevitable. But to package even a Madonna work in an extra dimension as itself (as a whole) a signifier, that is the birdcage. To view an artwork in this way is to alienate it from itself. As soon as any artwork is taken as representing a group of people, or as a sign of something other than the artwork, a circle has been drawn in an extra plane which is not among the dimensions of the artwork. The focus is no longer on the work's dynamic interactions, the multidimensional movement of moments in the understanding of the artwork, its internal open-ness to itself and to the world. It feels good to step back and "put the work into perspective." It seems to open wider horizons and a more comprehensive understanding, producing a kind of pleasure which motivates the diastolic movement of thought toward breadth, as opposed to its systolic movement toward depth. Depth nowadays is so out of fashion that it can seem comic: the half- mad scholar peering intently through bubble-lensed glasses at some object which is, because it is always part of a more comprehensive landscape, tainted with insignificance. If Modernism is a movement toward depth, Postmodernism flees outward. The price of this diastole is a loss of focus that entails loss of being. Once the artwork is packaged, wrapped in a dimension external to it, we can attach a handle and carry it around. We can put it on a shelf or in a bin. We can judge it by its wrapper: This is Monie Love the Nice Afro-American Female Rapper; this is Gerardo the Egg; this is Madonna the sex symbol, Madonna the money machine, Madonna the feminist, Madonna the Bird. The wrapper can be complex, and can package an object in contradictory ways. Hostile hands have wrapped Milton Babbitt as the serial blight, the phallo-centric repressive power; people who know him (as I do) clothe him in the garments of a dedicated and caring mentor, the inspiration of generations of composers and theorists, the one who freed us to think, opening a space in what had been a musical environment even more stiflingly anti-intellectual than it is now. To some, Babbitt's music is "elitist," coldly cerebral, incomprehensible, and static, yet for others it is bubbling with energy, a non-hierarchical multidimensional network in which each element is highly polysemic, links stretching out in all directions: <2> Babbitt the Bouncing Bubi (his own term for serialism), exuberantly exemplifying in his music structures which are in fact incompatible with those of elitism and phallo-centric control. Wrappers come in a variety of albedos, a continuum from opaque to nearly transparent. The more a wrapper points outward, packaging its object as representing something outside the object, the more opaque the wrapper is. At the extreme, our gaze does not penetrate the wrapper, and no information escapes from within it -- a sort of Black Whole. Madonna the Hot, Babbitt the Cold, Beethoven the Great, all can be such opacities. Sometimes opacity inheres in the object, which is its own wrapper: Gerardo's Egg. A wrapper becomes translucent to the extent that it turns toward representing its inside, the artwork, and becomes a description of it. It "writes from" its content for us to read. In this category, to various degrees, fall my brief characterizations of Babbitt's Bouncing Bubi (the polysemic network), Madonna's Bird (the always disappearing lines of flight); and also Heinrich Schenker's analysis of Beethoven's Eroica, Richard Toop's analysis of Brian Ferneyhough's Lemma-Icon-Epigram, <3> and so on. No wrapping is transparent. Works of art, like people, are never adequately represented. They must be experienced in life-time, in the flux of moments that makes up their being. Every circumscription is reductive; representation is not presentation. Even if a wrapper were perfectly transparent, it would still seal off the artwork from us like cellophane around a pear. We can see the pear, but can't smell it or taste it. Music in particular, that non-visual art, is as intimate and immediate as the maternal breast. In an unusual passage, Lacan says about suckling: The proprioceptive sensations of sucking and grasping obviously form the basis of this experience's ambivalence, which arises from the [following] situation: the being who is absorbing is completely absorbed .... <4> And a little earlier in Lacan's essay: Traumatic or not, weaning leaves in the human psyche the permanent trace of the biological relation it interrupts. Indeed, that vital crisis is replicated in a crisis of the psyche, undoubtedly the first whose resolution will have a dialectical structure. For the first time, it would seem, a vital tension is resolved in a mental intention. <5> Thus we have moved from life engaged with itself, absorbing and being absorbed, through the weaning crisis to a mental intention. Intention as a model of understanding holds within its metaphor the arrow of sight, directed to a distant and distinct object. Lacan tries to work through the consequent dichotomy of ego and other in explicitly optical terms. The sovereignty of sight informs notions of understanding at even more basic levels, maintaining (for perhaps psychologically necessary reasons) the separation from the maternal breast. Lacan's master was Hegel, mediated by Kojeve, as Mikkel Borch-Jacobsen has shown; the rift appears in Hegel early on in the "education of the spirit": It is as a universal too that we utter what the sensuous [content] is. What we say is: 'This', i.e. the universal This; or, 'it is', i.e. Being in general. Of course we do not envisage the universal This or Being in general, but we utter the universal; in other words, we do not strictly say what in this sense-certainty we mean to say. But language, as we see, is the more truthful; in it, we ourselves directly refute what we mean to say, and since the universal is the true [content] of sense- certainty and language expresses this true [content] alone, it is just not possible for us ever to say, or express in words, a sensuous being that we mean. <6> Hegel puns on the German "Meinung" to underline the private, and therefore incommunicable, nature of meaning in relation to "sense- certainty": what's mine cannot be yours. The optical separation is projected onto language by Hegel in a way that will reverberate through twentieth-century philosophy (recall only Wittgenstein!). Indeed, as we have seen, to signify is to be circumscribed, cut off from the world by a higher-dimensional agency, wrapped up for use. But art, and music in particular, is not the kind of entity that should expect such "to-handed" treatment, or that can survive it. Music shows a way out of the hall of mirrors, but only if we listen to it. <7> In order to see our way clear we should, before listening to what the audible has to say, get in touch with touch. Touch is the most reciprocal of the senses. To touch is to be touched. Separation is impossible. Touch has location, but is always immediate. Moreover, touch is the medium of agency: it is ultimately through touch that we act on the world, and the world acts on us. Merleau-Ponty, in his sympathetic posthumous book Le visible et l'invisible, tries to work his way through and out of and around the optical conundrums of subject and object, reflection and intuition. <8> The primary tools he develops for digging us out are, firstly, a validation of "la foi perceptive," a faith of and in perception which is related to the problem of Hegel's discarded unutterable unintelligible sensuous; and secondly, a method of philosophical interrogation: ...philosophy interrogates perceptive faith -- but neither expects nor receives an answer in the ordinary sense, because its question would not be satisfied by the unveiling of an unknown variable or invariant, and because the existing world exists in the interrogative mode. Philosophy is perceptive faith asking itself about itself.<9> For Merleau-Ponty, interrogation is the mode not only of philosophy, but of life, replacing the pure subjective negativity that drives existentialism from some early moments of Hegel through Sartre. If we are ourselves in question in the very course of our life, it is not because a central non-being threatens at each moment to withdraw its consent from being; it is because we ourselves are a single continuous question...a perpetual enterprise of putting ourselves back in place among the constellations of the world, and putting things [in the world] into place within our dimensions. <10> Inevitably, Merleau-Ponty is led to touch, describing at last ...a true touch of touch, when my right hand touches my left hand while feeling things, [a touch] by which the "touching subject" passes over to the rank of the touched, descends among things, so that touch constitutes itself from the midst of the world and as in things. <11> This leads Merleau-Ponty, towards the end of his book, to characterize the world-that-includes-us as flesh ("chair"), neither matter, spirit, nor substance, but an "element," a "general thing, half-way between the spatio-temporal individual and the idea, a kind of incarnated principle that imports a style of being everywhere it is part of being." <12> Instead of the intersubjective, we have "intercorporeality" ("intercorporeite"). <13> If my left hand can touch my right hand while it feels tangibles, ...can turn back on my right hand its [own] palpation, why, touching the hand of an other, wouldn't I touch in it the same power of marrying things that I touched in my own? <14> We have to ask music some very intimate questions. How does music feel when it entwines with its listener like two bodies sliding over and around each other? Exactly what is involved in this sensuous act, and what does time have to do with it? Does music think while it feels? Not all sound is music. Sound is naturally musical but may be turned to other uses. Speech packages sounds in opaque wrappers in order to make signifiers out of them, introducing the optical separation into sound. To the extent that texted music is speech, it is a mixed-realm art form like the mixed-media music video. The properly musical component is mixed with a semiotic component which is visual, either explicitly so in the case of the music video, or indirectly through the optical separation induced on sound by speech. If I wet my finger, I can rub a clear spot on the opaque wrapper of some speech-sound, such as "I." By rubbing hard enough, I can make a hole in the wrapper. Through this hole, the signifiance of "I" can leak out, its wrapper dissolved, and I find myself surrounded by and surrounding the music of "I." Ah -- eh -- eee. Around me, when I really get to know "I," are several pitched components moving in independent rhythms. These are physically caused by, and their rhythms are related to, the movements of the tongue, jaw, and lips in a mouth producing this sound. At first blush, "I" may seem only a sequence of two sound-qualities, ah and eee, with a hint of a middle sound, eh, at least implicit. By living with this sound long enough and attending to it carefully, it is possible to hear a counterpoint of at least two areas of pitch in motion. The changing relation of the two, when combined with an underlying, relatively static sound, composes an overall trajectory that can be chunked into the simplistic sequence of the ah, eh, eee. Even the underlying sound changes and reveals its own complexity: its shocking, explosive beginning and evaporative end, and the steady granularity that sustains it. Even more: the shocking beginning hesitates as it explodes, the steady granularity has blemishes and wavers, and so on. "I" is a musical composition. Its decomposition and reconstitution are a matter of everyday technique -- both musical and technological -- for composers of computer music. "I" is a relatively simple composition, and can be part of much more complex compositions such as "silent" and "time," which in turn may be composed into more complex music. For example, my composition Miranda might be described as the music of "time" embedded in the music of "silent." It is possible to compose sound in its musical nature and in its symbolic aspect at the same time, and in the same sounds. The two realms coexist in the same medium. The structure of musical sounds is musical, and the structure of the play of these same sounds as sonic signifiers can also be musical, though it may hover between poetry and music. It can be interesting to counterpoint the two structures of sounds-as-signifiers and sounds-as-musical-sounds, and a number of contemporary composers have been doing this, including (to mention only a few) John Cage, Kenneth Gaburo, Benjamin Boretz, Charles Dodge, Paul Lansky, and myself. Poetry is of course concerned with sound and rhythm as well as meaning. There is an intricate rhythm of alliteration and assonance overwebbing the words in the quantitatively metric elegiac distichs of Propertius, for example. Contemporary sound poetry goes a long way toward music. Perhaps the early twentieth- century French "lettriste" poets reached an extreme in the deconstruction of the semeiotic, though they generally had tin ears and remained fixed in the visual. <15> The nonlinear printed verbal productions of contemporary composer J. K. Randall look like poetry on the page, but feel like music when read, even though their nonlinearity often makes it impracticable to read them aloud. <16> If it is possible to make a structure of signifying sounds that is musical, how can we locate the distinction between music and poetry, or are they indifferent? The answer to this question lies in time. The time in music is an intimate time, a lived time, a "real" time. I have described musical time more fully elsewhere, telling the story of how a listener, Mary, lives herself alongside of the music. <17> Human life and music listened to by that life do not run parallel in straight lines never meeting, but rather intertwine closely, touching each other all over, each penetrating and being penetrated by the other, so that while they touch they almost fuse into one entity, one life-music or music-life. All the complexities of human being-in-time are there for music's being- in-life and life's being-in-music. Afterwards, when the music is over, we can step back and look at it, establishing that optical separation which is needed for one mode of understanding. We can then talk about the music with each other. I can hold a monologue in myself about the music, revolving its image, polishing and refining its facets, adjusting its balance. I can take out my rock collection and play with it, comparing one musicolith with others, sorting and arranging. I can even join a society of musicolithologists. But during the time I am coupled with the music, there is little or no semeiosis going on. The music and I are too involved with one another for a space to open up between us at any time, so that I could constitute a separate it as a sign. I am, so to speak, rapt, but not wrapping. Nor am I rapping. There is in music-time no monologue in me about the music which is linguistic, no logos in mousike. Those who sat upon the Delphic tripod over a Gaea cleft for Apollo were trained to speak during the divine afflatus, but they never made sense. It was the priests of Apollo who, like latter-day psychomusicometricians, stood apart watching the Pythoness in her trance: it was they who pretended to make sense of her protocol report of her experience. The experience of music affords a person the chance to think without language, without snipping the experience into discrete "segments" wrapped up into "signifiers," and free of the consequent machinery of negation, polar oppositions such as subject/object, and the whole permutational heap of linguistic gravel whose constant grinding can be music to nobody's ears. Language is all very well if one wishes to communicate. Music theory is about communicating about music, using some kind of language. But music itself is not "about" communication; the whole category of "being about" does not apply within it, except in ancillary ways (such as music composed partly out of ready-made signifiers, the music poetry discussed above). The connections between this moment of music and other moments of music, between this move in the music and that move in my life now or at some other time, such connections are immediate and intimate, like touch. They are not mediated by semeiosis. What some analyst might later (after the music) describe as a repetition of a motive such that the second instance makes a reference to the first, wrapping each instance in an opacity that points or receives -- this experience feels quite different in music-time. <18> Neither "instance of the motive" is wrapped, even in cellophane; both are experienced fully, and when I taste that other motive, its juices run down my chin. My mouth waters all the more during the second bite. I am not even sure when the first bite leaves off and the second begins; the taste lingers in my mouth so that the first mouthful is, in a way, still present during the second. This is not to say that the two experiences are not discriminated. On the contrary, the analysis of "I" showed how much discrimination lives in even a musical micro-composition. However, it is a discrimination that does not wrap, but leaves each discriminable open in as many ways as can be discriminated. Boundaries shift and overlap. All sorts of discriminables combine freely, promiscuously, polymorphically, not bound to respect presets, naked to each other. This is not the Kleiderphilosophie of semeiosis. What a strange new world! Is it really possible to live and think in music without negation and the polarities? Wilson Coker, a music theorist and aesthetician, tried to construct a Peircian semiotics for music. <19> He saw clearly that his premises entailed that music be internally a linguistic discourse, including the logic that underlies language. His attempts to provide interpretations of logical relations within music founder on the rock of negation. Tchaikovski's crashing orchestral chord does not musically negate, or contradict, the pianissimo descending bassoon solo that immediately precedes it. It is not the case that one is true and the other, false. <20> They coexist, elements of each circulating freely in the other; yet they are distinct, and their qualities are specifically determinate to a high degree. It is worth noting that musical qualities, unlike qualities of painting or sculpture or dance or theater or literature, have found many fruitful mathematical models to fit their structures. They are quantitatively discriminable. The authority of Boethius and Cassiodorus handed down to the Middle Ages this perception, that there is a difference between the realms of number (music, arithmetic, geometry, astronomy) and those of language and meaning, the "triviales artes verborum" (grammar, rhetoric, dialectic). The reasoning-within-music that goes on is precise and elaborate, a sensuous mathematics, a calculus of life. We value the complex richness of that musical reasoning and the stimulating strangeness of the encounters it provides. Because the music and my life are entwined like two strands of genetic material, each serves as a template for the other, so that in a real sense the quality of my life is the quality of the music, and the quality of the music is the quality of my life. If the music cannot support a complex adventure, it is my life that becomes banal. If I do not perceive the surrounding maze of cultural limitations constructed out of the lines drawn by the judgments of Minos, I will be content with a music that contents itself with musical convention. No doubt this is the more comfortable position for all concerned. The half-beast at the heart of the maze, with its well-known affinity for human flesh, only becomes dangerous if it shuts its eyes and tries to feel its way out of the maze, living the sensuous mathematics of music, thinking its way musically past the lines drawn by a discrimination that erects walls. For this the half-beast requires a music of great complexity, depth, and the power of originality. Discrimination without negation is a different kind of difference. It is a difference that does not draw the line, that does not step back in order to point, to throw out an ob-ject and put it in its place, in perspective. It does not point at all -- within music there can be no "j'accuse." The world of thought within music is not divided into truths and untruths, sheep and goats, the permitted and the forbidden. <21> There is no logical entailment enforcing its iron law in music-time. Instead there is a dance of molecular and molar reconstitution, a continual intimate renegotiation of what is, a spirit reaching eagerly forward to whatever the next moment may bring, like a happy child waking to each new day. The music may be sombre, tragic, agonized, but the underlying compact is pleasure, the sensuous pleasure of life in a richly diverse environment. After surrounding music with so many metaphors, dare I evert the metaphors to suggest that the individual person in modern, or postmodern, social and political life might benefit from thinking in ways that are not linguistic, but musical? <22> Notes 1. Readers will recognize that the terms of this discussion of Madonna are drawn from A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia by Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1987). 2. Thanks to a conversation with Marion Guck for this image. 3. Perspectives of New Music 28/2 (Summer 1990): 52-101. 4. Mikkel Borch-Jacobsen, Lacan: The Absolute Master, translated by Douglas Brick (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1991), 67. The original reference is Jacques Lacan, Les complexes familiaux dans la formation de l'individu (Paris: Navarin Editeur, 1984), 29-30. 5. Borch-Jacobsen, Lacan, 68. The original reference is Lacan, Les complexes familiaux, 27-28. 6. G. W. F. Hegel, The Phenomenology of the Spirit, translated by A. V. Miller (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977), 60. 7. Richard Rorty has explored the wider history of opticalism and representation and has advocated a "philosophy without mirrors" in Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979). 8. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Le visible et l'invisible, ed. Claude Lefort (Paris: Editions Gallimard, 1964). Translated by A. Lingis, (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1968). 9. Merleau-Ponty, Le Visible et l'invisible, 139. (Translations here from this book are my own.) 10. Merleau-Ponty, Le Visible et l'invisible, 140. 11. Merleau-Ponty, Le Visible et l'invisible, 170. 12. Merleau-Ponty, Le Visible et l'invisible, 184. 13. Merleau-Ponty, Le Visible et l'invisible, 185. 14. Merleau-Ponty, Le Visible et l'invisible, 185. The unfinished, posthumous Le Visible et l'invisible, which began in vision, ends with a brave but, for me, unconvincing attempt to constitute the world by reconstructing the realm of the visible along the lines of touch. The book pays virtually no attention to sound. 15. Jean-Paul Curtay, La poİsie lettriste (Paris: Editions Seghers, 1979). 16. There is a sample analysis and a bibliography of these J. K. Randall pieces in my article "Aspects of Musical Explanation," Perspectives of New Music 17/2 (Spring 1979): 204-224. 17. "Repetition," Contemporary Music Review, forthcoming. 18. There are all sorts of problems with such an analysis. The resemblance of the two motives does not entail a reference of one to the other, and even in this context of discourse about music it seems superfluous to invoke reference. Furthermore, the underlying idea of what repetition is is devastatingly naive (see "Repetition"). 19. Wilson Coker, Music and Meaning: A Theoretical Introduction to Musical Aesthetics (NY: The Free Press, 1972). See also my review in Perspectives of New Music 11/1 (Fall 1972): 255-258. 20. Coker, Music and Meaning, 122. 21. On logical segregation's inappropriateness for music, see my "Notes on Methodology in Music Theory," Journal of Music Theory 33/1 (1989): 143-154. 22. The ideas presented in the later part of this paper resonate strongly with those of the brilliant earlier writings of Julia Kristeva, as expressed in her work such as ªLa sİmiologie: Science critique et/ou critique de la scienceº (in Thİorie d'ensemble, Paris, 1968), La rİvolution du langage poİtique (Paris: ‰ditions du seuil, 1974), and Powers of Horror: An Essay on Abjection (New York: Columbia University Press, 1982, translated by Leon Roudiez). However, I did not wish to adapt her commitment in these writings to a triple braid of Marxism, Freudianism, and semiotics whose machinery, while impressive, seems to work too smoothly, and whose implications I cannot entirely share. I do share her focus on the semiotics of creative İnonciation rather than the packaged İnoncİ, and my model of music as asignifying ªpre-positº quantitative touch parallels her Platonic ªchora.º Seattle, April 1991